Here again is Rashmun, in my opinion a very promising Indologist, and an erudite rationalist skeptic, with typical gusto, taking an analytical swipe at the pretensions and motives of the legendary Upanishadic ideologue and theoretician, Yajnavalkya.
In the process, what you will notice below is an excellent rendition of an analysis of history and philosophy that uses the method of 'progression of the relations of production in shaping culture of a society'. This is much like the dialectical method of historical analysis pioneered by Karl Marx, and reproduced very ably in the context of Indian ancient history by the great historian, DD Kosambi.
Without wasting any further time in effusive introduction, here is the opinion piece, with nothing more than my highlighting of some high points of Rashmun's analysis
Yajnavalkya and the Material Requirement of an Upanishadic Idealist
The secret wisdom of the Upanishads is imagined to have the most wonderful power of
its own. This power is so 'great' that it promises not merely the worldly
things like cattle, offspring and fame; it can even assure something
which nothing else can.
In a famous story of the Upanisad (Brihad Aranyaka Upanishad iv.5.3-4), Yajnavalkya--about to retire--wants to have his property settled among his two wives Katyayani and Maitreyi:
Then said Maitreyi, 'If now, Sir, the whole earth filled with wealth be mine, would i be immortal thereby?'
'No', said Yajnavalkya, 'as the life of the rich, even so would your life be. Of immortality, however, there is no hope through wealth.
Then said Maitreyi, 'What should I do with that through which I may not be immortal? What you know, Sir, that indeed tell me.'
'No', said Yajnavalkya, 'as the life of the rich, even so would your life be. Of immortality, however, there is no hope through wealth.
Then said Maitreyi, 'What should I do with that through which I may not be immortal? What you know, Sir, that indeed tell me.'
This delights Yajnavalkya, and he initiates his wife into the secret knowledge he possesses.
The importance of this story for illustrating the new Upanishadic
attitude is rightly emphasized. A considerable number of Upanishadic
passages assert that the secret wisdom of the age promises immortality.
But let us return to Yajnavalkya's story.
The word used for immortal in the story is 'amrta'. The early Rig
Vedic poets are aware of this word no doubt. But they use it
rhetorically, usually to describe euphoria induced by the intoxicating
drink, soma; but the idea of 'secret wisdom' leading to immortality
never occurs to them, nor the idea of 'property settlement' in the
Upanishadic sense.
They do not have property as Yajnavalkya does and hence have no opportunity to cultivate the cult of secret wisdom.
They do not have property as Yajnavalkya does and hence have no opportunity to cultivate the cult of secret wisdom.
Yajnavalkya's property, whatever be its source is obviously relieving him of the problem of
maintaining himself by his own manual labour. How can Yajnavalkya,
without being thus relieved, devote himself to the cult of pure
consciousness? The basic requirement for this is leisure enough for the
purpose.
The contempt for the verdict of practice, on which the idealist outlook so vitally depends throughout its Indian career, can be possible for the philosopher only in so far as he is relieved of the basic responsibility of practical life--in short, in so far as he is ensured of the leisured existence.
The contempt for the verdict of practice, on which the idealist outlook so vitally depends throughout its Indian career, can be possible for the philosopher only in so far as he is relieved of the basic responsibility of practical life--in short, in so far as he is ensured of the leisured existence.
The material conditions in which the early Vedic poets live do
not permit them the the luxury of a leisured existence. With their
control over nature comparatively rudimentary, they cannot but be
obsessed with the problem of physical survival--a problem which is
solved in ancient society mainly by collective functioning.
The devotion of a selected few of the community to the cultivation of pure speculation is not yet objectively possible, for the community does not produce enough surplus to meet their material needs.
The devotion of a selected few of the community to the cultivation of pure speculation is not yet objectively possible, for the community does not produce enough surplus to meet their material needs.
In contrast in Upanishadic India (around the eighth and seventh century BC), things are different. There is considerable progress in the control over nature, thanks mainly to the introduction of iron implements on some scale and the improved technique of agriculture and handicrafts, which are now added to cattle-raising.
Human labor acquires the ability to produce much more than is
necessary for its bare maintenance. At the same time, the products of labor do not go to the laborers themselves; or in the words of the
early Vedic poets, they are not 'shared out' amongst the tribesmen. In
fact, this act of 'sharing out' is so important to the early Vedic poets
that they in their mythological imagination it is raised to the status
of veritable deities. They call these deities Bhaga and Amsa, literally
'the share'.
In Upanishadic India, however, the surplus produced by the direct producers is usurped by the kings and nobles.
In Upanishadic India, however, the surplus produced by the direct producers is usurped by the kings and nobles.
But to the collection of these taxes he shall always pay particular attention. He shall live on the surplus.
The accumulation of this surplus makes the kings and nobles
enormously wealthy in terms of the age. Depending on this surplus to
maintain themselves on a grand scale, they have all the leisure of life
to pursue and patronize the cult of pure consciousness. The kings
surround themselves by their flatterers (rajanya bandhu) and are often
described in the Upanishads as taking very keen interest in philosophical
discourses. But this does not mean they have the monopoly of the
'secret wisdom'. Outside the circle of the nobility, there are persons
with exceptional gifts claiming profounder wisdom endowed with more
imposing power.
Such a one was the 'great' Yajnavalkya.
Attracted by the magical potency of Yajnavalkya's wisdom--and above all perhaps by the rumour that this wisdom even ensures immortality or escape from death--one of the prosperous kings of the age, Janaka of Videha, is only too eager to part with a substantial portion of his wealth to the philosopher as payment for being initiated into the secret wisdom. Without being a plunderer of the surplus of the direct producers, Yajnavalkya thus becomes entitled to a part thereof.
Nothing is more attractive for the kings than the prospect of
overcoming death or attaining immortality, a fascination prevalent
amongst the wealthy rich even today, some of whom have paid vast sums of
money to have their bodies preserved in the hope that they may be
brought back to life in the future after science has advanced far enough
to be able to do so. This is basically also the same temptation that
leads the Pharaohs of Egypt to waste colossal amount of wealth to build
pyramids. Compared to the Pharaohs, the kings of the petty Upanishadic
states have far less wealth. But that is not the point. The point is
that for these kings also the temptation of overcoming death is
irresistible. They pay for it according to their means.
All this does not mean that for Yajnavalkya and his
co-philosophers the promise of immortality ensured by their secret
wisdom is necessarily a sales talk. It may as well be a part of their
make-belief. But whether make-belief or not, it does pay. And because it
pays, it can relieve the philosopher of the problem of maintaining
himself by his own labor. It even enables Yajnavalkya to amass
considerable property before his retirement.
For Yajnavalkya, it is quite logical to tell his wife that this
property does not ensure immortality; that immortality is ensured only
by his secret wisdom. Why else should his patron agree to pay him so
well for being initiated into the secret wisdom? However, what
Yajnavalkya does not add is that though this property does not ensure
immortality, it can and does ensure leisure for cultivating the cult of
pure wisdom. Without the solid support of the material wealth--the grand
gift of the patron--the alternative for him is working for a living.
But with the life of manual labor, Yajnavalkya's philosophy of pure
contemplation does not fit. From this point of view, therefore,
Yajnavalkya's worldly assets are not so unconnected with his world
denying philosophy as he would like his wife to believe.
Thus for understanding Yajnavalkya and his philosophy it is
necessary to take note of his property and understand its sources. Where
does it come from? The Upanisads are not at all vague about this. Here
is a typical description of the general setting of his philosophical
discourse (Brihad Aranyaka Upanisad iv.1.1):
Janaka, king of Videha, was seated. Yajnavalkya came up. To him the king said, 'Yajnavalkya, what brings you here? Is it because you want cattle or hair-splitting discussions?'
'Indeed both, your majesty', he said.
'Indeed both, your majesty', he said.
Metaphysically the cattle--like everything else in the world--are unreal no doubt. But these are not to be ignored for without these the meta-physician is not assured of his leisured existence which enables him to spin the world denying philosophy of Upanishads and Vedanta.
No comments:
Post a Comment